Copenhagen interpretation

The Copenhagen interpretation is a collection of views about the meaning of quantum mechanics, stemming from the work of Niels Bohr, Werner Heisenberg, Max Born, and others.Features common across versions of the Copenhagen interpretation include the idea that quantum mechanics is intrinsically indeterministic, with probabilities calculated using the Born rule, and the principle of complementarity, which states that objects have certain pairs of complementary properties that cannot all be observed or measured simultaneously.Copenhagen-type interpretations hold that quantum descriptions are objective, in that they are independent of physicists' personal beliefs and other arbitrary mental factors.From 1922 through 1925, this method of heuristic corrections encountered increasing difficulties; for example, the Bohr–Sommerfeld model could not be extended from hydrogen to the next simplest case, the helium atom.[9] Quantum mechanics cannot easily be reconciled with everyday language and observation, and has often seemed counter-intuitive to physicists, including its inventors.[note 1] The ideas grouped together as the Copenhagen interpretation suggest a way to think about how the mathematics of quantum theory relates to physical reality.[10][11] At the 1927 Solvay Conference, a dual talk by Max Born and Heisenberg declared "we consider quantum mechanics to be a closed theory, whose fundamental physical and mathematical assumptions are no longer susceptible of any modification.The purpose of the book seems to me to be fulfilled if it contributes somewhat to the diffusion of that 'Kopenhagener Geist der Quantentheorie' [Copenhagen spirit of quantum theory] if I may so express myself, which has directed the entire development of modern atomic physics.The term 'Copenhagen interpretation' suggests something more than just a spirit, such as some definite set of rules for interpreting the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics, presumably dating back to the 1920s.[3] It appears that the particular term, with its more definite sense, was coined by Heisenberg around 1955,[16] while criticizing alternative "interpretations" (e.g., David Bohm's[17]) that had been developed.[20] Before the book was released for sale, Heisenberg privately expressed regret for having used the term, due to its suggestion of the existence of other interpretations, that he considered to be "nonsense".[21] In a 1960 review of Heisenberg's book, Bohr's close collaborator Léon Rosenfeld called the term an "ambiguous expression" and suggested it be discarded.Generally, Copenhagen-type interpretations deny that the wave function provides a directly apprehensible image of an ordinary material body or a discernible component of some such,[43][44] or anything more than a theoretical concept.[54] In metaphysical terms, the Copenhagen interpretation views quantum mechanics as providing knowledge of phenomena, but not as pointing to 'really existing objects', which it regards as residues of ordinary intuition.[55] The metaphysical question is sometimes asked: "Could quantum mechanics be extended by adding so-called "hidden variables" to the mathematical formalism, to convert it from an epistemic to an ontic theory?"[60]: 248  Prominent physicists associated with Copenhagen-type interpretations have included Lev Landau,[60][61] Wolfgang Pauli,[61] Rudolf Peierls,[62] Asher Peres,[63] Léon Rosenfeld,[3] and Ray Streater.[73][74] The extremely small de Broglie wavelength of objects with larger mass makes experiments increasingly difficult,[75] but in general quantum mechanics considers all matter as possessing both particle and wave behaviors.They argued that no action taken on the first particle could instantaneously affect the other, since this would involve information being transmitted faster than light, which is forbidden by the theory of relativity.Bohr concluded that EPR's "arguments do not justify their conclusion that the quantum description turns out to be essentially incomplete.Bohr and Heisenberg advanced the position that no physical property could be understood without an act of measurement, while Einstein refused to accept this.The most famous product of his efforts to argue the incompleteness of quantum theory is the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen thought experiment, which was intended to show that physical properties like position and momentum have values even if not measured.[60]: 189–251 Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker, while participating in a colloquium at Cambridge, denied that the Copenhagen interpretation asserted "What cannot be observed does not exist".Steven Weinberg writes that the traditional presentation gives "no way to locate the boundary between the realms in which [...] quantum mechanics does or does not apply.Rudolf Peierls noted that "the observer does not have to be contemporaneous with the event"; for example, we study the early universe through the cosmic microwave background, and we can apply quantum mechanics to that just as well as to any electromagnetic field.[67] Physicists who have suggested that the Copenhagen tradition needs to be built upon or extended include Rudolf Haag and Anton Zeilinger.[87][91] Under realism and determinism, if the wave function is regarded as ontologically real, and collapse is entirely rejected, a many-worlds interpretation results.It attributes not only a wave function to a physical system, but in addition a real position, that evolves deterministically under a nonlocal guiding equation.For example, David Bohm and Alfred Landé both wrote textbooks that put forth ideas in the Bohr–Heisenberg tradition, and later promoted nonlocal hidden variables and an ensemble interpretation respectively.[60]: 453  John Archibald Wheeler began his career as an "apostle of Niels Bohr";[94] he then supervised the PhD thesis of Hugh Everett that proposed the many-worlds interpretation.[97] Other physicists, while influenced by the Copenhagen tradition, have expressed frustration at how it took the mathematical formalism of quantum theory as given, rather than trying to understand how it might arise from something more fundamental.
The Niels Bohr Institute in Copenhagen
Niels Bohr and Albert Einstein , pictured here at Paul Ehrenfest 's home in Leiden (December 1925), had a long-running collegial dispute about what quantum mechanics implied for the nature of reality.
Quantum mechanicsSchrödinger equationIntroductionGlossaryHistoryClassical mechanicsOld quantum theoryBra–ket notationHamiltonianInterferenceComplementarityDecoherenceEntanglementEnergy levelMeasurementNonlocalityQuantum numberSuperpositionSymmetryTunnellingUncertaintyWave functionCollapseBell's inequalityCHSH inequalityDavisson–GermerDouble-slitElitzur–VaidmanFranck–HertzLeggett inequalityLeggett–Garg inequalityMach–ZehnderPopperQuantum eraserDelayed-choiceSchrödinger's catStern–GerlachWheeler's delayed-choiceOverviewHeisenbergInteractionMatrixPhase-spaceSchrödingerSum-over-histories (path integral)Klein–GordonRydbergInterpretationsBayesianConsistent historiesde Broglie–BohmEnsembleHidden-variableSuperdeterminismMany-worldsObjective-collapseQuantum logicRelationalTransactionalVon Neumann–WignerRelativistic quantum mechanicsQuantum field theoryQuantum information scienceQuantum computingQuantum chaosEPR paradoxDensity matrixScattering theoryQuantum statistical mechanicsQuantum machine learningAharonovBlackettde BroglieComptonDavissonEhrenfestEinsteinEverettFeynmanGlauberGutzwillerHilbertJordanKramersLandauMoseleyMillikanPlanckSimmonsSommerfeldvon NeumannWignerZeemanZeilingerNiels BohrWerner HeisenbergMax BornindeterministicBorn rulecounterfactual definitenessstochasticclassical physicsMax Planckblackbody radiationAlbert Einsteinphotoelectric effectPeter Debyespecific heatHendrika Johanna van Leeuwendiamagnetismhydrogen atomArnold SommerfeldBohr modelrelativistic effectshelium atomtreatment of electron behaviormatricesErwin SchrödingerprobabilitiesNiels Bohr InstituteCopenhagenDenmarkhis instituteSolvay ConferenceUniversity of ChicagoThe Physical Principles of the Quantum TheoryDavid BohmLéon RosenfeldAsher PeresN. David MerminRichard Feynmancorrespondence principleHans PrimasRoland OmnèsHeisenberg cutobservationcollapseseigenstateobservableMach–Zehnder interferometerobserverwave–particle dualityprobabilitymeasurement of a quantum systemWave function collapseWolfgang PauliHidden-variable theoryepistemicJ.S. BellMax JammerLev LandauRudolf PeierlsRay Streaterthought experimentsuperselection ruleWigner's friendAlice and Bobinformation theoryDouble-slit experimentinterferephotoncomplementarity principlestream of particlesde Broglie wavelengthentangled stateBoris PodolskyNathan Rosentheory of relativityPhysical ReviewcomplementaryPaul Ehrenfestlong-running collegial disputeAbraham PaisEinstein–Podolsky–Rosen thought experimentCarl Friedrich von WeizsäckerJohn BellSteven Weinbergquantum cosmologycosmic microwave backgroundsuperconductorInterpretations of quantum mechanicsensemble interpretationquantum information theoryrelational quantum mechanicsRudolf HaagAnton Zeilingerrealismdeterminismmany-worlds interpretationobjective collapse theoryBohmian mechanicstransactional interpretationAlfred LandéJohn Archibald WheelerE. T. Jaynesquantum foundationsBohr–Einstein debatesEinstein's thought experimentsFifth Solvay ConferencePhilosophical interpretation of classical physicsPhysical ontologyPopper's experimentVon Neumann–Wigner interpretationSolvay CongressGbur, Gregory J.Faye, JanStanford Encyclopedia of PhilosophyStudies in History and Philosophy of Modern PhysicsBibcodeOmnès, RolandOmnès, R.European Journal of PhysicsStapp, Henry PierceThe Journal of Mind and BehaviorZeilinger, Antonvan der Waerden, B. L.Bernstein, JeremyAmerican Journal of PhysicsSocial Studies of SciencePhilosophy of ScienceMehra, J.Rechenberg, H.The MonistWeinberg, StevenHanson, Norwood RussellCiteSeerXKragh, H.Perspectives on ScienceHistorical Studies in the Physical and Biological SciencesRosenfeld, LéonNatureScheibe, ErhardCramer, John G.Reviews of Modern PhysicsBell, JohnPhysics WorldBohr, NielsPhysical Review APeres, AsherMermin, N. DavidPhysics TodayHeisenberg, WernerPauli, WolfgangEnz, C. P.Heisenberg, W.Born, M.ScienceBritish Journal for the Philosophy of ScienceSchilpp, P. A.Zeh, H. DieterFoundations of PhysicsZurek, Wojciech H.Physical Review DPhysics ReportsJammer, M.Jammer, MaxReports on Progress in PhysicsPeierls, RudolfKluwerStreater, R. F.Zeilinger, A.Proceedings of the American Philosophical SocietyContemporary PhysicsRosenfeld, L.Physical Review LettersEinstein, A.Podolsky, B.Rosen, NPais, AbrahamSpekkens, Robert W.Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part AHaag, RudolfThe European Physical Journal HHohenberg, P. C.van Fraassen, Bas C.Prescod-Weinstein, ChandaGleick, JamesWheeler, John ArchibaldNew York TimesJaynes, E. T.Zurek, W. H.Faye, J.Fine, ArthurWheeler, J. A.Bulletin of the Atomic ScientistsMargeneau, H.Timeline ComplementarityGround stateExcited stateDegenerate levelsZero-point energyQuantum stateSymmetry in quantum mechanicsFormulationsMatrix mechanicsPath integral formulationPhase spaceMajoranaRarita–SchwingerObjective collapseBell testDelayed-choice quantum eraserWheeler's delayed choiceQuantum biologyQuantum chemistryQuantum differential calculusQuantum dynamicsQuantum geometryQuantum measurement problemQuantum mindQuantum stochastic calculusQuantum spacetimeTechnologyQuantum algorithmsQuantum amplifierQuantum busQuantum cellular automataQuantum finite automataQuantum channelQuantum circuitQuantum complexity theoryQuantum cryptographyQuantum electronicsQuantum error correctionQuantum imagingQuantum image processingQuantum informationQuantum key distributionQuantum logic gatesQuantum machineQuantum metamaterialQuantum metrologyQuantum networkQuantum neural networkQuantum opticsQuantum programmingQuantum sensingQuantum simulatorQuantum teleportationQuantum fluctuationCasimir effectQuantum gravityin popular cultureQuantum mysticism